Letter: Why the War Crimes Act is just
Your support helps us to tell the story
From reproductive rights to climate change to Big Tech, The Independent is on the ground when the story is developing. Whether it's investigating the financials of Elon Musk's pro-Trump PAC or producing our latest documentary, 'The A Word', which shines a light on the American women fighting for reproductive rights, we know how important it is to parse out the facts from the messaging.
At such a critical moment in US history, we need reporters on the ground. Your donation allows us to keep sending journalists to speak to both sides of the story.
The Independent is trusted by Americans across the entire political spectrum. And unlike many other quality news outlets, we choose not to lock Americans out of our reporting and analysis with paywalls. We believe quality journalism should be available to everyone, paid for by those who can afford it.
Your support makes all the difference.Sir: Geoffrey Wheatcroft ('An act of vengeance, not justice', 15 December), pleads that the central issue behind the War Crimes Act 1991 is a matter of justice. In constructing his case he rehearses the whole gamut of argument adduced by the opponents of the legislation, from the most insidious ('several countries were pushed . . .') to the principled invocation of the rule of law.
The gist of his case is that the Act contravenes the most basic element of our system of justice - including the requirement of fairness - which it is the purpose of the rule of law to protect. It is precisely because of the rule of law that we must pass legislation such as the War Crimes Act.
It is not the case that the Act is 'a flagrant case of retroactive legislation'. Retroactivity refers to the subsequent criminalisation of an act that was lawful at the time it was committed. To be fair to Mr Wheatcroft, he prefers to think of genocidal crimes as merely 'revolting deeds', thus implying that the cold-blooded and systematic murder of thousands of innocent people was not a crime at the time such deeds were committed. Quite the contrary, both by the domestic laws of all civilised countries and by contemporary international law, war crimes of the kind committed by the Nazis and their willing collaborators were unlawful and constituted murder.
Second, he asserts that the Act in some way changes the rules of evidence and identification. Again incorrect: there is nothing in the Act to support such a bizarre contention. To the contrary, the Act introduces safeguards for the accused - thus prosecutions require the consent of the Attorney General, and where a notice of transfer had been issued the defence have a right of appeal (to the Crown Court) for the case to be dismissed for want of sufficient evidence.
However, the principled objection to the Act is said to concern the rule of law, understood as a set of juristic precepts guaranteeing fairness to the accused. In the light of the above points Wheatcroft's argument finally fails. But there is a deeper meaning to the rule of law: it can also be characterised as representing the ideals underpinning our system of justice as a whole.
In this sense, the purpose of law is not only to guarantee basic rights but also obligations to each other as civilised human beings. For the system of justice to fail to respond to crimes such as those involved in the Holocaust seriously undermines the integrity of the whole system. It also sends a message to the perpetrators of such unspeakable crimes - past, present and future - that their misdeeds will go unpunished by civilised legal orders.
Yours faithfully,
TONY RICHARDSON
Lecturer in Law
University of Sheffield
Sheffield
15 December
Join our commenting forum
Join thought-provoking conversations, follow other Independent readers and see their replies
Comments